Author Archives: Majken Hirche

Heraclitus: Greek Text and English Translation

Original Greek text : Diels; English translation : John Burnet (1912)

Click to open .pdf: Heraclitus

Further text on Heraclitus:

The Encyclopædia Britannica Eleventh Edition (1910–1911) : HERACLITUS (Ἡράκλειτος; c. 540-475 B.C.), Greek philosopher, was born at Ephesus of distinguished parentage. Of his early life and education we know nothing; from the contempt with which he spoke of all his fellow-philosophers and of his fellow-citizens as a whole we may gather that he regarded himself as self-taught and a pioneer of wisdom. So intensely aristocratic (hence his nickname ὀχλολοίδορος, “he who rails at the people”) was his temperament that he declined to exercise the regal-hieratic office of βασιλεύς which was hereditary in his family, and presented it to his brother. It is probable, however, that he did occasionally intervene in the affairs of the city at the period when the rule of Persia had given place to autonomy; it is said that he compelled the usurper Melancomas to abdicate. From the lonely life he led, and still more from the extreme profundity of his philosophy and his contempt for mankind in general, he was called the “Dark Philosopher” (ὁ σκοτεινός), or the “Weeping Philosopher,” in contrast to Democritus, the “Laughing Philosopher.” κακοὶ μάρτυρες Heraclitus is in a real sense the founder of metaphysics. Starting from the physical standpoint of the Ionian physicists, he accepted their general idea of the unity of nature, but entirely denied their theory of being. The fundamental uniform fact in nature is constant change (πάντα χωρεῖ καὶ οὐδὲν μένει); everything both is and is not at the same time. He thus arrives at the principle of Relativity; harmony and unity consist in diversity and multiplicity. The senses are “bad witnesses” (κακοὶ μάρτυρες); only the wise man can obtain knowledge. To appreciate the significance of the doctrines of Heraclitus, it must be borne in mind that to Greek philosophy the sharp distinction between subject and object which pervades modern thought was foreign, a consideration which suggests the conclusion that, while it is a great mistake to reckon Heraclitus with the materialistic cosmologists of the Ionic schools, it is, on the other hand, going too far to treat his theory, with Hegel and Lassalle, as one of pure Panlogism. Accordingly, when he denies the reality of Being, and declares Becoming, or eternal flux and change, to be the sole actuality, Heraclitus must be understood to enunciate not only the unreality of the abstract notion of being, except as the correlative of that of not-being, but also the physical doctrine that all phenomena are in a state of continuous transition from non-existence to existence, and vice versa, without either distinguishing these propositions or qualifying them by any reference to the relation of thought to experience. ” Every thing is and is not'”; all things are, and nothing remains. So far he is in general agreement with Anaximander (q.v.), but he differs from him in the solution of the problem, disliking, as a poet and a mystic, the primary matter which satisfied the patient researcher, and demanding a more vivid and picturesque element. Naturally he selects fire, according to him the most complete embodiment of the process of Becoming, as the principle of empirical existence, out of which all things, including even the soul, grow by way of a quasi condensation, and into which all things must in course of time be again resolved. But this primordial fire is in itself that divine rational process, the harmony of which constitutes the law of the universe (see LOGOS). Real knowledge consists in comprehending this all-pervading harmony as embodied in the manifold of perception, and the senses are “bad-witnesses,” because they apprehend phenomena, not as its manifestation, but as “stiff and dead.” In like manner real virtue consists in the subordination of the individual to the laws of this harmony as the universal reason wherein alone true freedom is to be found.” The law of things is a law of Reason Universal (λόγος), but most men live as though they had a wisdom of their own.” Ethics here stands to sociology in a close relation, similar, in many respects, to that which we find in Hegel and in Comte. For Heraclitus the soul approaches most nearly to perfection when it is most akin to the fiery vapour out of which it was originally created, and as this is most so in death, ” while we live our souls are dead in us, but when we die our souls are restored to life.” The doctrine of immortality comes prominently forward in his ethics, but whether this must not be reckoned with the figurative accommodation to the popular theology of Greece which pervades his ethical teaching, is very doubtful. The school of disciples founded by Heraclitus flourished for long after his death, the chief exponent of his teaching being Cratylus. A good deal of the information in regard to his doctrines has been gathered from the later Greek philosophy, which was deeply influenced by it. BIBLIOGRAPHY.—The only authentic extant work of Heraclitus is the περὶ φύσεως. The best edition (containing also the probably spurious Ἐπιστολαί) is that of I. Bywater, Heracliti Ephesii reliquiae (Oxford, 1877); of the epistles alone by A. Westermann (Leipzig, 1857). See also in A. H. Ritter and L. Preller’s Historia philosophiae Graecae (8th ed. by E. Wellmann, 1898); F. W. A. Mullach, Fragm. philos. Graec. (Paris, 1860); A. Fairbanks, The First Philosophers of Greece (1898); H. Diels, Heraklit von Ephesus (2nd ed., 1909), Greek and German. English translation of By water’s edition with introduction by G. T. W. Patrick (Baltimore, 1889). For criticism see, in addition to the histories of philosophy, F. Lassalle, Die Philosophie Herakleitos’ des Dunklen (Berlin, 1858; 2nd ed., 1892), which, however, is too strongly dominated by modern Hegelianism; Paul Schuster, Heraklit von Ephesus (Leipzig, 1873); J. Bernays, Die heraklitischen Briefe (Berlin, 1869); T. Gomperz, Zu Heraclits Lehre und den Uberresten seines Werkes (Vienna, 1887), and in his Greek Thinkers (English translation, L. Magnus, vol. i. 1901); J. Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy (1892); A. Patin, Heraklits Einheitslehre (Leipzig, 1886); E. Pfleiderer, Die Philosophie des Heraklit us von Ephesus im Lichte der Mysterienidee (Berlin, 1886); G. T. Schäfer, Die Philosophie des Heraklit von Ephesus und die moderne Heraklilforschung (Leipzig, 1902); Wolfgang Schultz, Studien zur antiken Kultur, i.; Pythagoras und Heraklit (Leipzig, 1905); O. Spengler, Heraklit. Eine Studie ilber den energetischen Grundgedanken seiner Philosophie (Halle, 1904); A. Brieger, “Die Grundzüge der heraklitischen Physik ” in Hermes, xxxix. (1904) 182-223, and “Heraklit der Dunkle” in Neue Jahrb. f. das klass. Altertum (1904), p. 687. For his place in the development of early philosophy see also articles IONIAN SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY and LOGOS. Ancient authorities: Diog. Laert. ix.; Sext. Empiric, Adv. mathem. vii. 126, 127, 133; Plato, Cratylus, 402 A and Theaetetus, 152 E; Plutarch, Isis and Osiris, 45, 48; Arist. Nic. Eth. vii. 3, 4; Clement of Alexandria, Stromata, v. 599, 603 (ed. Paris). (J. M. M.)

Parmenides: Greek Text and English Translation

Original Greek text : Diels; English translation : John Burnet (1892)

Click to open .pdf: Parmenides

Further text on Parmenides:

The Encyclopædia Britannica Eleventh Edition (1910–1911) : PARMENIDES OF ELEA (Velia) in Italy, Greek philosopher. According to Diogenes Laertius he was “in his prime” 504-500 B.C., and would thus seem to have been born about 539. Plato indeed (Parmenides, 127 B) makes Socrates see and hear Parmenides when the latter was about sixty-five years of age, in which case he cannot have been born before 519; but in the absence of evidence that any such meeting took place this may be regarded as one of Plato’s anachronisms. However this may be, Parmenides was a contemporary, probably a younger contemporary, of Heraclitus, with whom the first succession of physicists ended, while Empedocles and Anaxagoras, with whom the second succession of physicists began, were very much his juniors. Belonging, it is said, to a rich and distinguished family, Parmenides attached himself, at any rate for a time, to the aristocratic society or brotherhood which Pythagoras had established at Croton; and accordingly one part of his system, the physical part, is apparently Pythagorean. To Xenophanes, the founder of Eleaticism—whom he must have known, even if he was never in any strict sense of the word his disciple—Parmenides was, perhaps, more deeply indebted, as the theological speculations of that thinker unquestionably suggested to him the theory of Being and Not-Being, of the One and the Many, by which he sought to reconcile Ionian “monism,” or rather “henism,” with Italiote dualism. Tradition relates that Parmenides Lamed laws for the Eleates, who each year took an oath to observe them. Parmenides embodied his tenets in a short poem, called Nature, of which fragments, amounting in all to about 160 lines, have been preserved in the writings of Sextus Empiricus, Simplicius and others. It is traditionally divided into three parts—the “Proem,” “Truth” τὰ πρὸς ἀλήθειαν), and ” Opinion” (τὰ πρὸς δόξαν). In “Truth,” starting from the formula ” the Ent (or existent) is, the Nonent (or non-existent) is not,” Parmenides attempted to distinguish between the unity or universal element of nature and its variety or particularity, insisting upon the reality of its unity, which is therefore the object of knowledge, and upon the unreality of its variety, which is therefore the object, not of knowledge, but of opinion. In “Opinion ” he propounded a theory of the world of seeming and its development, pointing out however that, in accordance with the principles already laid down, these cosmological speculations do not pretend to anything more than probability. In spite of the contemptuous remarks of Cicero and Plutarch about Parmenides’s versification, Nature is not without literary merit. The introduction, though rugged, is forcible and picturesque; and the rest of the poem is written in a simple and effective style suitable to the subject. Proem.—In the “Proem” the poet describes his journey from darkness to light. Borne in a whirling chariot, and attended by the daughters of the sun, he reaches a temple sacred to an unnamed goddess (variously identified by the commentators with Nature, Wisdom or Themis), by whom the rest of the poem is spoken. He must learn all things, she tells him, both truth, which is certain, and human opinions; for, though in human opinions there can be no “true faith,” they must be studied notwithstanding for what they are worth. Truth.—”Truth” begins with the declaration of Parmenides’s principle in opposition to the principles of his predecessors. There are three ways of research, and three ways only. Of these, one asserts the non-existence of the existent and the existence of the non-existent [i.e. Thales, Anaximander and Anaximenes suppose the single element which they respectively postulate to be transformed into the various sorts of matter which they discover in the world around them, thus assuming the non-existence of that which is elemental and the existence of that which is non-elemental]; another, pursued by ” restless ” persons, whose ” road returns upon itself,” assumes that a thing “is and is not,” “is the same and not the same ” [an obvious reference, as Bernays points out in the Rheinisches Museum, vii. 114 seq., to Heraclitus, the philosopher of flux]. These are ways of error, because they confound existence and non-existence. In contrast to them the way of truth starts from the proposition that ” the Ent is, the Nonent is not.” On the strength of the fundamental distinction between the Ent and the Nonent, the goddess next announces certain characteristics of the former. The Ent is uncreated, for it cannot be derived either from the Ent or from the Nonent; it is imperishable, for it cannot pass into the Nonent; it is whole, indivisible, continuous, for nothing exists to break its continuity in space; it is unchangeable [for nothing exists to break its continuity in time]; it is perfect, for there is nothing which it can want; it never was, nor will be, but only is; it is evenly extended in every direction, and therefore a sphere, exactly balanced; it is identical with thought [i.e. it is the object, and the sole object, of thought as opposed to sensation, sensation being concerned with variety and change]. As then the Ent is one, invariable and immutable, all plurality, variety and mutation belong to the Nonent. Whence it follows that all things to which men attribute reality, generation and destruction, being and not-being, change of place, alteration of colour are no more than empty words. Opinion.—The investigation of the Ent [i.e. the existent unity, extended throughout space and enduring throughout time, which reason discovers beneath the variety and the mutability of things] being now complete, it remains in “Opinion” to describe the plurality of things, not as they are, for they are not, but as they seem to be. In the phenomenal world then, there are, it has been Thought [and Parmenides accepts the theory, which appears to be of Pythagorean origin], two primary elements—namely, fire, which is gentle, thin, homogeneous, and night, which is dark, thick, heavy. Of these elements [which, according to Aristotle, were, or rather were analogous to, the Ent and the Nonent respectively] all things consist, and from them they derive their several characteristics. The foundation for a cosmology having thus been laid in dualism, the poem went on to describe the generation of “earth and sun, and moon and air that is common to all, and the milky way, and furthest Olympus, and the glowing stars”; but the scanty fragments which have survived suffice only to show that Parmenides regarded the universe as a series of concentric rings or spheres composed of the two primary elements and of combinations of them, the whole system being directed by an unnamed goddess established at its centre. Next came a theory of animal development. This again was followed by a psychology, which made thought [as well as sensation, which was conceived to differ from thought only in respect of its object] depend upon the excess of the one or the other of the two constituent elements, fire and night. ” Such, opinion tells us, was the generation, such is the present existence, such will be the end, of those things to which men have given distinguishing names.” In the truism “the Ent is, the Nonent is not, ὄν ἔστι, μὴ ὄν οὐκ ἔστι, Parmenides breaks with his predecessors, the physicists on the Ionian succession. Asking themselves—What is the material universe, they had replied respectively—It is water, It is μεταξύ τι, It is air, It is fire. Thus, while their question meant, or ought to have meant, What is the single element which underlies the apparent plurality of the material world? their answers, Parmenides conceived, by attributing to the selected element various and varying qualities, reintroduced the plurality which the question sought to eliminate. If we would discover that which is common to all things at all times, we must, he submitted, exclude the differences of things, whether simultaneous or successive. Hence, whereas his predecessors had confounded that which is universally existent with that which is not universally existent, he proposed to distinguish carefully between that which is universally existent and that which is not universally existent, between ὄν and μὴ ὄν. The fundamental truism is the epigrammatic assertion of this distinction. In short, the single corporeal element of the Ionian physicists was, to borrow a phrase from Aristotle, a permanent οὐσία having πάθη which change; but they either neglected the πάθη or confounded them with the οὐσία. Parmenides sought to reduce the variety of nature “to a single material element; but he strictly discriminated the inconstant πάθη from the constant οὐσία, and, understanding by “existence” universal, invariable, immutable being; refused to attribute to the πάθη anything more than the semblance of existence. Having thus discriminated between the permanent unity of nature and its superficial plurality, Parmenides proceeded to the separate investigation of the Ent and the Nonent. The universality of the Ent, he conceived, necessarily carries with it certain characteristics. It is one; it is eternal; it is whole and continuous, both in time and in space; it is immovable and immutable; it is limited, but limited only by itself; it is evenly extended in every direction, and therefore spherical. These propositions having been reached, apart from particular experience, by reflection upon the fundamental principle, we have in them, Parmenides conceived, a body of information resting upon a firm basis and entitled to be called ” truth.” Further, the information thus obtained is the sum total of “truth”; for, as “existence” in the strict sense of the word cannot be attributed to anything besides the universal element, so nothing besides the universal element can properly be said to be “known.” If Parmenides’s poem had had “Being” for its subject it would doubtless have ended at this point. Its subject is, however, “Nature”; and nature, besides its unity, has also the semblance, if no more than the semblance, of plurality. Hence the theory of the unity of nature is necessarily followed by a theory of its seeming plurality, that is to say, of the variety and mutation of things. The theory of plurality cannot indeed pretend to the certainty of the theory of unity, being of necessity untrustworthy, because it is the partial and inconstant representation of that which is partial and inconstant in nature. But, as the material world includes, together with a real unity, the semblance of plurality, so the theory of the material world includes, together with the certain theory of the former, a probable theory of the latter. “Opinion” is then no mere excrescence; it is the necessary sequel to “Truth.” Thus, whereas the Ionians, confounding the unity and the plurality of the universe, had neglected plurality, and the Pythagoreans, contenting themselves with the reduction of the variety of nature to a duality or a series of dualities, had neglected unity, Parmenides, taking a hint from Xenophanes, made the antagonistic doctrines supply one another’s deficiencies; for, as Xenophanes in his theological system had recognized at once the unity of God and the plurality of things, so Parmenides in his system of nature recognized at once the rational unity of the Ent and the phenomenal plurality of the Nonent. The foregoing statement of Parmenides’s position differs from Zeller’s account of it in two important particulars. First, whereas it has been assumed above that Xenophanes was theologian rather than philosopher, whence it would seem to follow that the philosophical doctrine of unity originated, not with him, but with Parmenides, Zeller, supposing Xenophanes to have taught, not merely the unity of God, but also the unity of Being, assigns to Parmenides no more than an exacter conception of the doctrine of the unity of Being, the justification of that doctrine, and the denial of the plurality and the mutability of things. This view of the relations of Xenophanes and Parmenides is not borne out by their writings; and, though ancient authorities may be quoted in its favour, it would seem that in this case as in others, they have fallen into the easy mistake of confounding successive phases of doctrine, ” construing the utterances of the master in accordance with the principles of his scholar—the vague by the more definite, the simpler by the mere finished and elaborate theory ” (W. H. Thompson). Secondly, whereas it has been argued above that “Opinion” is necessarily included in the system, Zeller, supposing Parmenides to deny the Nonent even as a matter of opinion, regards that part of the poem which has opinion for its subject as no more than a revised and improved statement of the views of opponents, introduced in order that the reader, having before him the false doctrine as well as the true one, may be led the more certainly to embrace the latter. In the judgment of the present writer, Parmenides, while he denied the real existence of plurality, recognized its apparent existence, and consequently, however little value he might attach to opinion, was bound to take account of it : ” pour celui même qui nie l’existence réelle de la nature,” says Renouvier, ” il reste encore à faire une histoire naturelle de l’apparence et de l’illusion.” The teaching of Parmenides variously influenced both his immediate successors and subsequent thinkers. By his recognition of an apparent plurality supplementary to the real unity, he effected the transition from the ” monism ” or ” henism ” of the first physical succession to the “pluralism” of the second. While Empedocles and Democritus are careful to emphasize their dissent from “Truth,” it is obvious that “Opinion” is the basis of their cosmologies. The doctrine of the deceitfulness of “the undiscerning eye and the echoing ear” soon established itself, though the grounds upon which Empedocles, Anaxagoras and Democritus maintained it were not those which were alleged by Parmenides. Indirectly, through the dialectic of his pupil and friend Zeno and otherwise, the doctrine of the inadequacy of sensation led to the humanist movement, which for a time threatened to put an end to philosophical and scientific speculation. But the positive influence of Parmenides’s teaching was not yet exhausted. To say that the Platonism of Plato’s later years, the Platonism of the Parmenides, the Philebus and the Timaeus, is the philosophy of Parmenides enlarged and reconstituted, may perhaps seem paradoxical in the face of the severe criticism to which Eleaticism is subjected, not only in the Parmenides, but also in the Sophist. The criticism was, however, preparatory to a reconstruction. Thus may be explained the selection of an Eleatic stranger to be the chief speaker in the latter, and of Parmenides himself to take the lead in the former. In the Sophist criticism predominates over reconstruction, the Zenonian logic being turned against the Parmenides metaphysic in such a way as to show that both the one and the other need revision: see 241 D, 244 B seq., 257 B seq., 258 D. In particular, Plato taxes Parmenides with his inconsistency in attributing (as he certainly did) to the fundamental unity extension and sphericity, so that “the worshipped ὄν is after all a pitiful μὴ ὄν” (W. H. Thompson). In the Parmenides reconstruction predominates over criticism—the letter of Eleaticism being here represented by Zeno, its spirit, as Plato conceived it, by Parmenides. Not the least important of the results obtained in this dialogue is the discovery that, whereas the doctrine of the “one” and the “many” is suicidal and barren so long as the “solitary one” and the “indefinitely many” are absolutely separated (137 C seq. and 163 B seq.), it becomes consistent and fruitful as soon as a “definite plurality ” is interpolated between them (142 B seq., 157 B seq., 160 B seq.). In short, Parmenides was no idealist, but Plato recognized in him, and rightly, the precursor of idealism. BIBLIOGRAPHY.—The fragments have been skilfully edited by H. Diels, in Parmenides Lehrgedicht, griechisch u. deutsch (Berlin, 1897), with commentary; in Poetarum philosophorum fragmenta. with brief Latin notes, critical and interpretative (Berlin, 1901); and in Die Fragmente d. Vorsokratiker (Berlin, 2nd ed., 1906), with German translation); and Diels’ text is reproduced with a helpful Latin commentary in Ritter and Preller’s Historia philosophiae graecae (8th ed., revised by E. Wellmann, Gotha, 1898). The philosophical system is expounded and discussed by E. Zeller, D. Philosophie d. Griechen (5th ed., Leipzig, 1892; Eng. trans., London, 1881); by T. Gomperz, Griechische Denker (Leipzig, 1896; Eng. trans., London, 1901); and by J. Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy (London, 1908). For the cosmology, see A. B. Krische, D. theologischen Lehren d. griechischen Denker (Gottingen, 1840). On the relations of Eleaticism and Platonism, see W. H. Thompson, “On Plato’s Sophist” in the Journal of Philology viii. 303 seq. For other texts, translations, commentaries and monographs see the excellent bibliography contained in the Grundriss d. Geschichte d. Philosophie of Überweg and Heinze 10th ed., Berlin, 1909; Eng. Trans., London, 1880). (H. JA.)

ENFJ / ENFP Insincerity

“I warned you. I took you out to dinner to warn you of charm. I warned you expressly and in great detail. Charm is the great blight. It spots and kills anything it touches. It kills love; it kills art; I greatly fear, my dear Charles, it has killed you.” – Evelyn Waugh, Brideshead Revisited

It’s no secret that all types have liabilities that they need to overcome. Some MBTI resources touch upon the problems of given types (INTJs are know-it-alls, ESFPs are boastful and rash), but they do so only lightly as they cannot risk alienating people from a system that they simultaneously wish to evangelize, spread, and market.

In this article we will explore a typical problem area for ENFJs and ENFPs: That of sincerity. At first glance, this mention of sincerity as a problem area might strike us as odd. After all, these are the intuitive feeling types who are usually described as people’s persons. Most dramatically so in David Keirsey’s Please Understand Me, wherein he describes all NF-types as valuing sincerity, authenticity, and benevolence, but also so in Isabelle Myers’ Gifts Differing where she says that they “Value, above all, harmonious human contacts.”. – How, then, can these types possibly have problems with sincerity?

The premise for the assertion is that all ENs will have an easy time tuning into what people want while feeling types will naturally try to accommodate. In regards to smaller or insignificant matters this is insanely charming, and makes people around the ENF feel at ease, even valued. But when applied to larger, more serious issues, it is exactly these people pleasing tendencies that turn around and become a liability to the sincerity of these types. As one INTP succinctly put it:

“It can make it a bit more difficult for me to trust them, when I can’t determine if they’re committed to what they’re saying or not.”

Indeed, to put it short, it’s a blurry and often unconscious slide from the quality of pleasantness to the vice of insincerity, and ultimately hypocrisy. We are here speaking of hypocrisy in the sense of social hypocrisy, defined as the act of pretending to have beliefs, virtues and feelings that one does not truly possess. In practical terms, this can often take the form of agreeing to a certain viewpoint in one company or context, only to turn about and agree to the contrary a few hours later, perhaps even never to internalize either position fully. Ultimately, this amounts to the ENF not sticking to her word; neither to the group to whom it was uttered nor to themselves and yet the ENF probably won’t even recognize it because it was never their motivation in the first place; – they simply aimed to please.

By far the easiest cure here is simply to present a given predicament to the ENF in sufficiently neutral and dispassionate terms. This allows them little room for accommodation, thereby allowing you to gauge what they truly value, beyond their layers of people pleasing behaviour. In many cases this is actually the optimal approach to handling ENFs, as it is the least time-consuming and requires only minimal personal allegiance from the ENF. A notable exception is in the case of friends, however; in heart-warm relations this approach is truly a disservice, as it allows your ENF friends to retain their liability indefinitely, with you working around it rather than them working on it.

While there are many outwards similarities between the people pleasing behaviours of the ENFJ and the ENFP, we must also understand that the ENFJ and the ENFP are widely different personality types in the sense that one is governed by Extroverted Feeling (Fe) and the other by Extroverted Intuition (Ne). If you don’t know the concept of dominant functions already, I recommend that you look into it at some point in order to familiarize yourself further with the idea. For now, you can simply note that ENFJs purposefully apply their Extroverted Judgment in order to supply warmth and goodwill while ENFPs operate on impulsive energies that they erratically employ to entertain, hoping that others will like them.

Let us, then, examine each type in turn.

ENFJ – The Harmonizer

Within the MBTI, Feeling and Thinking are traditionally referred to as judging functions while Intuition and Sensation are traditionally referred to as perceiving functions. I will not go further into the reasoning behind this here (instead see the essay “Dominant Functions”). Consequently, like all judging functions, Extroverted Feeling is concerned with generating attitudes and value judgments towards the objects that surround it, while in fact it is the perceiving function does the actual observation and perceiving. For the ENFJ, the Perceiving function is Introverted Intuition (Ni), which means that their primary mode of perception is actually inwardly directed and as such the ENFJ’s observations are actually somewhat negligent of the external situation compared to types whose perceptive function is outwardly directed. There is indeed a trade-off here: At the cost of this negligence the ENFJ instead receives greater constancy instead and is thus capable of pursuing ideas and projects all the further.

Now the Feeling function generally operates based on value judgments; while Introverted Feeling (Fi) allows a person to know what they value, Extroverted Feeling (Fe) allows a person to adjust their behaviour to the needs of others. As with all types dominated by Feeling the ENFJ typically has a strong belief in their value judgments. But coming from Extroverted Feeling (Fe) these value judgments will tell the ENFJ nothing about their own needs and values beyond what they have internalized of their surroundings. Never the less, ENFJs tend to place great stock in the judgments generated by their Extroverted Feeling (Fe) because to the ENFJ these judgments will appear to be based purely on objective observations. Yet as perceiving functions tend to operate unconsciously, the observations that end up ringing true to the ENFJ and are in fact predetermined by the ENFJ’s personal standard of agreeable- / disagreeableness.

With the lack of Introverted Judgment, an ENFJ who has not developed his or her capacity for introspective reflection will unconsciously elevate the external situation to a tyrant of the psyche. These ENFJs will be so preoccupied with external situations that they will do everything in their power to honour whatever needs or wishes there contained therein (be they voiced or unvoiced), even to the extent of breaking a promise or being untrue to their own opinions.

As I mentioned earlier, the MBTI Literature already touches upon many of these points. Actually I believe the points above can be satisfactorily summarized in three compact quotes:

“Apparently the [ENFJ’s] urge to harmonize extends even to intellectual opinions. A very charming ENFJ who has been interested in type since her high-school days to me earnestly, ‘So-and-so asked me what I thought of type, and I didn’t know what to tell her, because I didn’t know how she felt about it.’” – Isabelle Myers, in Gifts Differing

“ENFJs have definite values and opinions which they’re able to express clearly and succinctly. These beliefs will be expressed as long as they’re not too personal. ENFJ is in many ways expressive and open, but is more focused on being responsive and supportive of others. When faced with a conflict between a strongly-held value and serving another person’s need, they are highly likely to value the other person’s needs.” – From Personalitypage.com

“All thinking that might disturb [the process of extroverted] feeling is suppressed. It is possible for [external situations] to become so important that constantly changing feeling states result in accordance with the changes in surroundings.” – C.G. Jung, in Psychological Types

Finally, on a more anecdotal note, I wish to offer the following story once told to me by an ENFJ:

“This co-worker of mine is slimy and slick, he’s very charming and funny but it’s obvious that he shouldn’t be trusted. He made a joke and I was the only that laughed. I didn’t think it was funny I just laughed because my other co-workers were giving him the cold shoulder. I don’t blame them; he’s not a nice person in my opinion.

When I think about most of my interactions with this guy, I know I give a different impression than what I feel. I don’t like him, have never liked him, but he would never guess it, or rather I’d go to great lengths to hide my true feelings for him.”

The best way for an ENFJ to grow beyond these liabilities is to ardently balance their Extroverted Feeling (Fe) with well-rounded introspective observations. With regards to the MBTI and the order of functions (again, see the essay “Dominant Functions”), this would mean nurturing Introverted Intuition (Ni) to grow beyond the point where its observational input is no longer a slave to the judgments of Extroverted Feeling (Fe).

An Exercise for ENFJs

The easiest way to bring about the growth of your Introverted Intuition is probably to cheat your Extroverted Feeling. Commit a day to solitude and while sitting there focus on the fact that you are not really alone but in fact you are there. Resist the urge to go out or contact friends, but externalize yourself instead: If you were sitting opposite your clone in the room, what would you do to please him or her? This then, is what you must do; be true to yourself and you will eventually realize that you bring needs and wants into a given situation yourself. It is not always about the wishes and needs of others.

ENFP – The Pleaser

As previously mentioned, ENFPs are somewhat different from ENFJs in the sense that ENFPs don’t have clear-cut and implicitly-understood value judgments to guide them. When we look at this in relation to the order of functions, we see that this is because the ENFP’s dominant function is Extroverted Intuition (Ne), whereas the ENFJ’s dominant function is Extroverted Feeling (Fe). The beautiful thing about Extroverted Intuition is its ability to react to external stimuli, offering all sorts of novel connections and theories, but Extroverted Intuition will never be able to provide Judgment. Lacking such outwards judgment themselves, the undifferentiated ENFP will all too often be forced to rely on others for approval and validation. ENFPs who exert this behaviour are only rarely prompted by insincerity, however, but in fact they do so because it is the only readily available way for them to feel good about themselves.

What’s worse; were the ENFJ can maintain a point of praise delivered onto them by others, and thus keep drawing satisfaction from it, the ENFP with its lack of judgment cannot keep a focused history and so they find it absolutely imperative to please everyone around them over and over. This is not all bad for the ENFP and all good for the ENFJ, however: If this lack of a focused history has a tendency to render the ENFP fickle it conversely has a tendency to render the ENFJ self-satisfied on the grounds of things long since past, perhaps, even to the degree of removing the ENFJs incentive for the real introspective work that precedes personal growth.

As we have seen this ENFP fickleness arises from a perpetual and partly subconscious thirst for emotional affirmation and personal validation. Coupled with typical Ne love of being the centre of attention, this leaves the ENFP in a situation where they will go to great lengths to obtain this admiration, and with such much value placed in accommodation and true judgment being so inaccessible to the, they tend to have an easy time valuing accommodation and the present situation over “distant” principles they just don’t perceive the insincerity and hypocrisy that invariably follows, thus rendering them social hypocrites in the eyes of more stern and principal onlookers.

Or take the following quote on a supposed ENFP:

[His] essential character flaw isn’t dishonesty as much as a-honesty. It isn’t that Clinton means to say things that are not true, or that he cannot make true, but that everything is true for him when he says it, because he says it. Clinton means what he says when he says it, but tomorrow he will mean what he says when he says the opposite.”

Now I will turn to a personal example. I do not expect anyone’s opinion to be swayed by personal anecdote; I provide the story to illuminate on the points above.

I once worked with an ENFP producing a television show. Our editor had aired some intentions of censorship regarding our show and its content, should it prove too radical. Not having signed anything, I knew that the intellectual copyright still pertained to us, the authors, and I made this ENFP promise me that we wouldn’t let ourselves be censored.

Then one morning my ENFP partner calls me and says that our editor has started editing our show out of her own volition. Maintaining that the editor has no right to do so without our approval I rush to the television station and prepare to browbeat the editor, only to discover that my ENFP partner had given the clear some 20 minutes prior, caving into accommodation-pressure from the editor.

To be fair, the part they ended up censoring wasn’t particularly good though. But that is another story.

The ENFP in question admits to having caved to accommodation pressure twice (first the easy thing to do was to make the promise, then the easy thing to do was to break it). He didn’t even know what his own position was, he said but the question remains if not having no opinion is simply another and more advanced form of accommodation, as no-opinion cannot collide with other peoples opinions thus creating social uncomfortability.

Concluding Assessment

ENFs themselves and they probably wont even recognize it because it isn’t their motivation. They set out to please or harmonize, but all too often loose themselves in the process. They merely aimed to please, but an evil done with good intent is still an evil, never the less.

Philosophically it is the problem of Dogville over again; the ENFP being the dog.

On a deeper psychological level, ENFX hypocrisy can be explained by the fact that ENFXs usually wallow in Fundamental Attribution Error. Being Extroverts they are more likely to explain their own actions by their environment, yet they attribute the actions of others to ‘innate characteristics’, thus leading towards judging others while justifying ones’ own actions. In other words, another prime example of hypocrisy.

Nietzsche once remarked that “man is the animal who can make promises”. Within the frame of the MBTI I take this to mean that man can manifest himself into a given situation by giving his word. This capacity embedded in man’s self-awareness which allows him to project his internal intentions awareness onto the external situation. Ironically enough, this means that a man with little natural regard for his internal world will regularly feel as if promises are something which the external world forces upon him: Like an animal will naturally identify with social (external/collectivist) needs or promises, that is, the anthill, the bee hive or the antelope herd.

One further remark on this matter pertains to the matter that the word responsible is composed of prefix re (meaning “to return, come back”) and sponsible meaning “to answer or promise”. From this matter we can deduce that being responsible in fact has to do with being able to internally identify with whatever word one has set out (or given) into the external world. If the counterweight of introverted cognition is missing, the ENF (or indeed any other person suffering similar problems) won’t perceive himself as untrue to his word but will instead see two external situations untrue to each other. If he hasn’t already, it is absolutely imperative for the ENF who treasures his personal development overcome this.

Tyvesidet terning fra oldtidens Egypten

Kultur To årtusinder før nogen havde hørt om rollespilsfænomenet ’Dungeons & Dragons’ , spillede oldtidens egyptere et ukendt spil, som gjorde brug af den ikoniske 20-sidede terning.

Af Ryan Smith

Der er tale om samme type terning, som rollespilsnørder overalt i den vestiglige verden ruller med, når de skal spille ’Dungeons & Dragons.’ Faktisk er designet fuldstændig identisk. Terningen har ligget gemt i magasinerne på The Metropolitan Museum of Art, hvor kuratorerne ikke har kunnet se meningen med at udstille den. Nu har rollespilsnørder fundet frem til terningen via et online-katalog over museets gemmer, og terningen udstilles nu ivrigt på online-medier som io9 og Cnet News.

Terningen er ca. 2,5 centimeter høj og menes at stamme fra den ptolomæiske periode af Egyptens historie. Det vil sige fra perioden med de græske faraoer, som blev installeret i kølvandet på Alexander den Stores erobring af Egypten i 332 f.Kr. og som varede helt til Caesars invasion af Egypten (samt erobring af Cleopatra) i 30 f.Kr.

Terningen er lavet af det mineralske materiale serpentin, og formodningen om, at terningen skulle stamme fra den græske periode af Egyptens historie underbygges endvidere af, at symbolerne for eta, theta og epsilon er klart synlige på terningen.

Hvilket spil de gamle egyptere har spillet med terningen, er dog endnu ukendt.

Jung and the Scarab: A Tale of Synchronicity

The following famous tale was featured in Jung’s Synchronicity: An Acausal Principle (1952):

A young woman I was treating had, at a critical moment, a dream in which she was given a golden scarab. While she was telling me this dream, I sat with my back to the closed window. Suddenly I heard a noise behind me, like a gentle tapping. I turned round and saw a flying insect knocking against the window-pane from the outside. I opened the window and caught the creature in the air as it flew in. It was the nearest analogy to a golden scarab one finds in our latitudes, a scarabaeid beetle, the common rose-chafer (Cetonia aurata), which, contrary to its usual habits, had evidently felt the urge to get into a dark room at this particular moment. I must admit that nothing like it ever happened to me before or since.

Synchronicity: An Acausual Principle (1952)
The Collected Works of C.G. Jung
Paragraph 843
Princeton University Press Edition

Jung Misunderstood Zen Buddhism

When most people think of Jung and Zen Buddhism today, they probably think of Jung’s forword to D.T. Suzukis writings. Yet to the serious student, that is far from the whole story of Jung’s studies in Buddhism.

Shinichi Hisamatsu (1889-1980) was a professor of philosophy and religion at Kyoto University. He was originally a pupil of the philosopher Nishida Kitaro, who founded the school of philosophy in Kyoto. In 1915, when Hisamatsu had finished his university degree and thirty-one years old, Nishida sent him to Myoshin monastery to train in Zen. Hisamatsu was later known for his unusually deep understanding of Zen. He started the FAS Society (Formless, All Self), which, has been a source of inspiration and dialogue center between East and West for more than thirty years.

The dialogue between Jung and Hisamatsu took place in 1960, and was printed in the English-speaking Japanese magazine Psychologia Vol. 11 (1968), that is, eight years after the actual conversation took place. The editor of Psychologia, Sato Koji found the original dialogue between Jung and Hisamatsu so interesting that he arranged to have it translated into English and published in the journal.

The dialogue is interesting, chiefly because it showcases the difference between Jung’s analytical psychology and the “psychology” of Zen Buddhism. At the time (1960) Jung appeared to be taken in with the possibility of Zen Buddhism essentially being an Eastern variant of his own school of psychology, a view that very few Jungians will attempt to profess today. There have been many attempts to find parallels between Zen and Jungian psychology, all in all these attempts have failed to bear much fruit for the simple reason that Zen has a much wider scope than the subject’s therapeutic awareness of unconscious experiences and the integration of the psyche.

In the dialogue says Hisamatsu that it is only after the release of what we commonly call “self” that Zens “true self” appears. Then comes Jung with the strange and incomprehensible view that Hisamatsus “true self” should be understood as klesha (i.e. impurity), while his own notion of the “true self” corresponds to the atman or purusa. It’s hard to see how one can possibly explain away this misunderstanding. The idea that Zen’s “true self” should correspond to klesha is almost unbearable, for klesha means mental impurity or disorder, and is responsible for the causes of our suffering is ignorance, selfishness, greed, hatred and stupidity etc. Zen training aims raise awareness of reality, which will lead to the realization of the “true self” that was previously hidden by klesha which could in some sense be identifies with the illusory (or false) self.

Furthermore, Zen Buddhism’s “true self” is without form or substance and has no contents that are separate from any exterior “non-self”. Against this conception of self, Jung postulated that the self has definite contents and – even though part of a person’s unconscious might be collective in nature – it is still differentiated on the basis of the individual’s culture. It is hard to see how Jung’s “self” is synonymous with the Zen’s “true self”, as he postulates that it is. I do not think that Jung ever understood what the “true self” of Zen really is.

Kant vs. Berkeley – Does the World go Away when we aren’t Looking?

How do we know that reality is still there if no one is there to observe it?

The idea that the world goes away when we aren’t looking is commonly called Subjective idealism or Empirical idealism. (I.e. your mind forms subjective ideas about reality which then appear to you as matter. If your mind isn’t there, maybe the matter won’t be there either.)

If we take the idea of Subjective idealism to mean that we cannot know anything about the objective world, then Kant encroached a great deal on this problem by taking a step back and saying that we can know some things to be absolutely true no matter what (e.g. a triangle has three sides). So even if our experience of the world is totally screwed up, the concepts will still be right.

Kant then suggested that you can start from certain concepts (triangles have three sides) and then extend that certitude to fields like math. (You don’t know that 2+2 = 4 like you know that a triangle has three sides, but once you have tested 2+2 it’s always = 4.) This then forms a synthesis of ideal and actual knowledge that never fails for anyone. So we can also know that with certainty.

People coming after Kant then went even further and said that in the same way that 2+2 is always = 4, we can move even further out of our heads and into the world. Every time somebody analyses water it turns out that it is H2O and never anything else.

In this way we can start with pure conceptual knowledge in our heads (triangles have three sides) and then creep further and further out into reality. That the empirical world appears with regularity and appears to have a consistency no matter who is observing it is a huge deal in favor of empirical reality being objective and hence in some sense actually there. Confronted with this argument, the opponents of the 1700s could only intervene to say that the source of this objectivity was God who made a “consensus reality” for all observers. Even back then it was obvious that this was a bullshit argument.

So even though we cannot 100% refute that reality goes away when we are not looking, we can get very far towards proving that it doesn’t go away. (Certainly we can do way better than those who say reality is subjective.) This does not mean that we get to experience all of reality entirely as it exists on its own terms (we don’t), but it means that we get to experience a good deal of reality with a regularity that is shared by all subjects and which appears to be internally consistent. Empirical reality cannot reasonably be said to be subjectively created by our minds although it could be said to be interpreted by our minds, i.e. warped to fit with the mind’s nascent need to see things as structured in space, time, quantity, etc. – categories which would not necessarily be there if there was no observer.

Thus, if a tree falls in the forest and no one hears it, it is overwhelmingly likely that it will make a sound, though with no observer present to cognitively structure the experience, there may well be no tree, nor sound to be discerned as entities standing apart from the rest of the totality of reality.